Seeing our blog nears its finale, I find myself sentimental. I must share, posting after Kim is my
favorite. Your questions provoke the
writing mind. (-:
Particularly, this stands out: “Does
believing or should-be-believing matter at all if we don’t have someone to
believe with or to tell our belief to, judge our belief against, etc?”
I had not before devoted much to
recognizing how large a role community plays
in rhetoric. After all, if the opinions,
consensus, and camaraderie of others were irrelevant, persuasion would go
job-searching. There would be no need to
convince others if creating larger networks and taskforces was unneeded. Rhetoric therefore, is not only evidenced in
every interaction and knowledge-making process, but is also the result of
intrinsic drives towards shared goals and purposes. We want
to agree with each other—otherwise persuasion would cease to exist. Argument, generally seen as representing human
strife and disparity, actually evidences a desire to see the same together, to concur. *insert head nod to Jim Corder.*
Which sounds all good, until Perelman
writes, “All intellectual activity which is placed between the necessary and
the arbitrary is reasonable only to the degree that it is maintained by
arguments and eventually clarified by controversies which normally do not lead
to unanimity” (p. 159). For those having
difficulty untangling P’s multi-layered sentences, what he seems to say is, “We
measure the reasonableness of thinking (and thus knowledge) to the extent we debate
it, usually ending in disagreement anyway.”
Real hopeful guy, this Perelman. Before
unwrapping the quote, I want to call out his spectrum-ends of “necessary” and “arbitrary.” It’s a curious binary, different from others
we have thus encountered. Rather than proposing
two fundamentally opposed ways of
thinking (square vs. groovy, rhetoricus
vs. seriousus, etc.), Perelman
presents the opposing ends of what we
think. At first, this seems viable
because we can distinguish between those which are necessary thoughts (to find
food, for example) and those which are arbitrary (is the dress white or blue?) But soon the line blurs—is intellectual
activity surrounding the concept of gravity arbitrary or practical? Yes, gravity is a conception based on human
observation and subjective reasoning, but it also plays out practically: “ouch,
shouldn’t have tried to fly off my dresser.”
I doubt intellectual activity will ever be definable on a neat, linear,
spectrum. Nice effort though,
Perelman.
What was I going to say before my tangent? Perelman writes that thoughts and perceptions
(intellectual activity) are only as reasonable (I read that as worthy) as we keep discussing them. Which makes sense, because the age-old
conversations, the ones we keep having over and over again (existentialism vs.
essentialism, role of logic, acceptable epistemologies, do souls exist, etc.) carry great
weights in meaning. If singular agreement
could be easily found, it would have. So
I’m thinking “yeah dude, I hear you” until he writes that those intellectual
concepts are eventually clarified through irreconcilable disagreement.
What does the inability to find
agreement clarify if not that both sides are correct simultaneously? Perhaps Perelman meant just that. For example, that nature and nurture both determine behavior and
personality. These huge questions are
clarified not by absolute disagreement, but by recognizing that the two
opposing answers are likely not polar opposites, but a simultaneous, multi-dimensional,
“stacked” answer. That rational thinking
and romantic thinking are two methods of understanding, both “true” in their
own right. It goes against human intuition
to imagine that two objects can occupy the same space at the same time, but that’s exactly how
we find clarity to complex questions—understanding how both sides can simultaneously
exist in the answer slot. If humankind, inherently
desiring agreement, can stand adamantly opposed, how can it not mean that both sides contain truth?
It's easy to throw punches at Perelman for his sentence-layering, which requires intense front-loading of information before delivering the punch line which
then subsequently changes all the previous clauses. Yet he communicates through a retrospective,
reframing, method. Call it dense, but
isn’t that how knowledge works? As we accrue
understanding, it causes what came before and seemed confusing to now enter the light. And then we know.
No comments:
Post a Comment